Sunday, November 23, 2014

Environment

Inclusion, according to Deleuze, is formed by the monad's apperception. Inclusion carries events into the monad,(1) enabling exo-relations and promtping individual manifestations. Because identity for the objectile is not a recipricol definition but always a vector,(2) perceptions advance differentially: infinitesimal variations of perceptions that develop inclusion.(3) Of the different types of inclusion(4) we are interested here in how the monad includes the world within itself. Consistent with the object-oriented position, there is no object which functions as a universal world, one that can contain all others. Despite the fact that, for Leibniz, every monad includes the whole world, the “the reason of the series... is not. The limit remains extrinsic and appears only in a harmony preestablished among the monads.”(5) In this formulation, every monad is a singular subject; however, these subjects are themselves without objects, “these are minute perceptions lacking an object, that is, hallucinatory microperceptions.”(6) Despite the inversion of intent, the result retains a correspondence with the object-oriented goal of “subjectless objects” because no monad is thrown under another subject as its correlate, but each exists only for itself.(7) What is changed is that there is no longer a guarantee nor a necessity of overall harmonious convergence across the totality of monads.

For Leibniz, the convergent harmonization of these series was required by the imperative of a single compossible world that is sharply delineated from all others. Deleuze, drawing from Riemannian manifolds, introduces “a fibered conception according to which 'monads' test the paths in the universe and enter in syntheses associated with each path... a world of captures instead of closures”(8) In this model “bifurcations, divergences, incompossibilities, and discord belong to the same motley world,”(9) or rather, a plurality of non-exclusive worlds.

to flickr
Fruit cultivation Wanmu Orchard, Guangzhou

The relation of object to world is a complex one; “there is always a double antecedence: the world is virtually first, but the monad is actually first.”(10) To clarify, we would say that the point of view of the monad precedes the individual object(11) as a potential series of interaction between the monad and surrounding objects, but that the world, or environment(12), that it occupies does not pre-exist as such. Part of the generative ability of objects includes their “active role in constructing their environment, both through determining relevancies in the environment and through actively changing their environment.”(13) For each and every object, therefore, there is a unique environment, which it includes.(14) However, in the same way that objects that become components of an assemblage do not give up their distinct identity or agency to become docile parts only, so do the environmental conditions “exceed the object, they are equally the conditions involved in other existing objects, and that cannot therefore be specified as belonging to that object alone, nor as terminating in it.”(15) In particular one can say that “while objects construct their openness to their environment, they do not construct the events that take place in their environment”(16) and relate to it in a feedback cycle of construction and constraint.(17) The need for objects to form “contingent strategies for contending with the environment”(18) constitutes the ground of exo-relations.

Though Deleuze prefers the metaphor of the fold to convey the complexly implicated interior of the monad,(19) the virtual dimension from which objects are unfolded is not a pre-individual stratum that is continuous like a sheet of fabric. Instead it is like an entangled knot or rhizome: not everywhere continuous but, through a complex selection, continuously interconnecting. “This genesis is a genesis from other objects or discrete individuals, and in many instances is productive of new individual entities.”(20) It is perhaps better to use Leibniz's own images of every portion of matter as teeming with individuals “like a garden full of plants and like a pond full of fishes”(21) in order to remind ourselves of the complex plenitude of components at every scale. As an alternative to assembling or constructing, then, we might speak of objects as 'cultivating' their environments.

Notes:

Wednesday, September 10, 2014

Monadology

Deleuze describes Leibniz's concept of the monad in similar language as “the autonomy of the inside”(1) and “a unity that envelops a multiplicity, this multiplicity developing the One in the manner of a “series.”(2) As a pure interiority, the monad is withdrawn from direct connections, which “must retain the distinction of its details and its own individuality in the hierarchy in which it enters.”(3) Again, there is agreement that local manifestations, or 'inclinations', of the monad are non-necessary(4) traits that occur as “an act, a movement, a change, and not the state.”(5) Inclinations are qualitative but not attributive, “the predicate is above all a relation and an event, and not an attribute,”(6) therefore predicates do not ground the monad, they are included in the monad. More than anything else, Deleuze emphasizes this point; it is established in the very first sentence, “The Baroque refers not to an essence but rather to an operative function”(7) and is adamantly repeated throughout his analysis: “Inflection is the event that happens to the line or to the point;”(8) “not defined by an attribute, but by predicates-as-events;”(9) “the spontaneity of manners replaces the essentiality of the attribute.”(10)

to flickr
Xiaozhoucun, Guangzhou

As these events proliferate, they gain series of entanglements with other objects whereby they extend into or over one another.(11) The way the monad includes its predicates determines a harmonization of the monad with the adjacent and component objects, with regard to the production of the world around it.(12) The monad's withdrawn virtual being—or its intrinsic singularities, to use Deleuze's term—generates the events that include relations within the object. Meanwhile there is a second, reflexive operation which directs these series of inclinations inward toward convergence as intensities.(13) As such, the propagation of relations is not a constriction of the object but a continuous prolongation(14) with regard to the world it engages. “Even compressed, folded, and enveloped, elements are powers that enlarge and distend the world.”(15) In the same way architecture extends into a frame that “itself becomes detached from the inside, and establishes relations with the surroundings so as to realize architecture in city planning.”(16)

The extension of monads and the inclusion of additional inflections gives the monad a changing 'texture' of qualities and potentials. “Extensions effectively are forever moving, gaining and losing parts carried away in movement; things are endlessly being altered; even prehensions are ceaselessly entering and leaving variable components.”(17) The example above from the Baroque bel composto illustrates how the object gains new arenas of influence as it attunes to new inflections. “This area of interindividual, interactive clustering is quite agitated, because it is an area of temporary appurtenances or of provisional possessions.”(18) Continouous differentiation of the developing assemblage feeds back into the withdrawn being of the object such that the object “no longer refers... to a relation of form-matter—but to a temporal modulation that implies as much the beginnings of a continuous variation of matter as a continuous development of form.”(19) Michael Guggenheim has demonstrated how architecture is incapable of being restricted to a single domain, but is always an object acting in multiplicity of associations,(20) making it uniquely suited to the model of the objectile,(21) where “fluctuation of the norm replaces the permanence of a law.”(22) Following this concept, we will show how architecture activates and intensifies the urban dynamic by including its perception of the unlocalizable rhythms of the city as inflected predicates.

Notes:

Sunday, July 20, 2014

Exterior Relations

Because objects cannot be reduced upwards into controlling structures nor downward atomistically into their parts, neither is there an a priori global container, “There is no world... that connects things together. All such connections must be emergent properties of the objects themselves.”(1) The internal withdrawal of objects and the location of their potency within the virtual clearly complicates the ways by which such connections are able to form. To remain consistent with the ontological formation advanced thus far, any possible relation forgoes direct contact: it must derive from the individual object and issue from its own agency,(2) Bryant proposes that exo-relations can be characterized as translations of information—with the understanding that “information is thus not something that exists in the world independent of the systems that 'experience' it, but is rather constituted by the systems that 'experience' it... Information is, as it were, a genuine event that befalls a substance or happens to a substance.”(3)

to flickr
Xiaozhoucun, Guangzhou

A few significant aspects of this concept are worth detailing. First, the information of a relation does not have its own, separate being, but is enacted by the emitting object as a property, a quality, or an event and received by the second object tin an act of sensing or perceiving: “information is object-specific, whereas the same perturbation can affect a variety of different objects while producing very different information for each object.”(4) Relations are highly sensitive to the affective capability of objects.(5) Second, because these information-events are translated into being only through the apperception of various objects, there is no 'original meaning' or 'pure interpretation'.(6) Third, in a nicely symmetrical moment, this fact holds true even for the originating object, from which the quality is a self-othering event.(7) (We can confirm this by following Deleuze's argument that the virtual does not in any way resemble the actual.(8)) Taken together, these points prevent the the relation-as-information from devolving into mere simulacra(9) thought instead “as force-signs of deterritorialization and of reterritorialization.”(10)

Meanwhile, objects are always joining together to form larger assemblages. In fact, Harman has written that “when two objects enter into genuine relation, even if they do not permanently fuse together, they generate a reality that has all of the features that we require of an object... they create something that has not existed before, and which is truly one.”(11) However, this would effectively reduce all relations to endo-relations and the assertion that “there are properties of objects that emerge as a result of the manner in which the object relates to other objects.”(12) would have to be modified to acknowledge that those properties occur only as the result of the top-down influence of a encompassing assemblage. Though we want to facilitate the production of new objects as much as possible, we will hold off from extending objecthood to such an extent, preferring to leave open the possibility of horizontal relations between objects that remain merely relations. Even stable patterns of relations should be permitted without automatically conflating the relationship with a new object.(13) Rather, a new object occurs “when exo-relations among other objects manage to attain operational closure such that their aggregate or multiple composition becomes capable of encountering perturbations as information in terms of their own endo-consistency.”(14) While this qualification risks being misinterpreted as saying that all objects are strictly defined intensionally, by a shared property or predicate, the earlier specification of the virtual proper being as a dimension subsequent to the individual, still allows objects to be defined extensionally by naming or enumeration as well.

The problems of external relation and the formation of new assemblages both raise questions about causality, or, the efficacy of assemblages. Timothy Morton seemingly implies that the withdrawal of objects away from one another produces a “disturbing illusory play of causality.”(15) This would be an understandable position if one focuses on the interior being within an object as a division “vertically from the implicate to the explicate.”(16) Through this lens it would appear that the virtual in an object acted upon constructs effects that are detached from their source. Rather, returning to the dictum that “difference is an activity... existence is thought as a sort of doing or movement,”(17) it is apparent that such a reading confuses the agency of the object with its reception. “No object can transfer a force to another object without that force being transformed in some way or another,”(18) but this does not mean that the force is not exerted or that the transference is only an illusion. The agency of an object is measured by its effecting of the world, a process that is always messy and complexly negotiated, not by distilling the legibility of intent away from any interferences.

In fact, the opposite is true. If there were a medium or metalanguage by which information were transferred without alteration, there would be no action—that is, no difference—remaining in the act itself but only within the mediator.(19) Just as all connections emerge from the objects themselves, so are communications produced through patterns of encounters, based on “the records of actions antecedent in the production of consequents.”(20) and are perpetually challenged by new divergences.(21) So too is causality not effected by the machinery of an underlying structure, but manifests as a phenomenon that emanates from and repositions objects in new spatio-temporal contexts.(22)

Notes:

Monday, June 9, 2014

Internal Existence

From the principle of redundant causality we know that “within open systems or entanglements of objects, the powers of discrete objects are often veiled or inactive.”(1) If these extensive entanglements were given the power of defining the identity of objects, they would never be capable of asserting clear independence, always remaining muddled, unable to identify whether an object exists or not, only able to suggest possible objects.(2) Furthermore, this would be akin to the ground differentiating from the object and would contradict the difference-in-itself. Thus, “objects must also be thought in terms of their endo-relations or their inter-ontic structure as radically independent of their exo-relations or their inter-ontic relations.”(3) The endo-relations of an assemblage encapsulated within the object form an interior existence which is never entirely accessible to an external object. This is considered a definitive property of objects: “there are no objects characterized by full presence or actuality. Withdrawal is not an accidental feature of objects... but is a constitutive feature of all objects regardless of whether they relate to other objects.”(4)

to flickr
near Wanmu Orchard, Guangzhou

Those aspects of an object which are not withdrawn but are accessible and relate to other objects, its qualities, are freed up from carrying the responsibly to define identity. Classical concepts of substance had difficulty splitting qualities from objects because there weren't any additional differentiations beyond the object's qualities to individuate it(5) but in an object-oriented ontology, “objects are not identical to their qualities but are rather the ground of qualities.”(6) They are no longer the building blocks or quanta of being, but actualizations of the object. “Objects can be fully concrete without locally manifesting themselves or actualizing themselves in qualities... Local manifestation is something that objects can do, but an object that does not locally manifest itself is not lacking in some way, nor is it somehow incomplete”(7) As such, extensities are not constrained to formal or necessary roles in the object, but can follow diverse potential behaviors(8) It is more appropriate, therefore, to think of an object's extensive qualities not ”as something an object possesses, has, or is, but rather as acts, verbs, or something that an object does.”(9) Qualities can be responsive to the idiosyncrasies of their contexts—both internal and external—in ways that properties of identity would resist.(10) Perceived from the point of view of two separate external relations, an object can even enact contradictory or incompossible qualities based on the properties “that emerge as a result of the manner in which the object relates to other objects.”(11)

Having peeled away the qualitative dimension, there remains the internal structure of the object. Object-oriented ontology contends that “objects are not merely aggregates of other objects, but have an irreducible internal structure of their own.”(12) This topological organization is not common for all or even a group of assemblages, which would suggest an organization based on a shared predicate,(13) nor is it fixed and immutable. In fact, the intensive is caught up in a transitional immediacy of a relation to its own indeterminancy. “withdrawn into an all-encompassing relation with what it will be. It is in becoming, absorbed in occupying its field of potential”(14) That is, while any transition within an assemblage's internal relations transforms the field of potential emergent properties, it still remains “an operationally closed object that relates to the sub-multiples of which it is composed or the multiples that it composes only in terms of its own internal organization”(15) and cannot be determinately indexed to anything outside itself.”(16) Mereologically, the object's internal being still remains independent from any assemblages it might be a part of and even those out of which it is composed.(17) It can be properly said that this independence exceeds everything that can be known about the object through its relations.(18)

This nonqualitative structure follows Deleuze's concept of the virtual,(19) however, Bryant critiques Deleuze's insistence that the virtual is pre-individual, arguing that “the virtual is not something that produces the individual, but rather must strictly be a dimension of the individual.(20) This is done to preserve the agency of the object in causal interactions and to locate production as an act of the individual rather than the individual as the residue of production.(21) This returns to the assertion earlier that to be is to make or produce difference. If objects are to exist, they do so as differentiation engines.(22) Bryant refers to this virtuality of the individual as the 'virtual proper being'.

Notes:

Tuesday, May 27, 2014

Object Oriented Philosophy

As the most active branch of what has been named Speculative Realism, object-oriented philosophy shares the realist(1) and anti-reductionist(2) positions of assemblage urbanism. Perhaps the best summary of the objective of object-oriented philosophy is the desire “to think a subjectless object, or an object that is for-itself rather than an object that is an opposing pole before or in front of a subject... an object for-itself that isn't an object for the gaze of a subject, representation, or a cultural discourse.”(3) Naturally, this attitude of “a universe made up of objects wrapped in objects wrapped in objects wrapped in objects”(4) lends itself well to a flat ontology like the one proposed by Manuel DeLanda(5) and covered in chapter one.(6) This can be seen in one of the core problematics of object-oriented philosophy, the question of access to objects:
“On the other hand, where the anti-realists have obsessively focused on a single gap between humans and objects, endlessly revolving around the manner in which objects are inaccessible to representation, object-oriented philosophy allows us to pluralize this gap, treating it not as a unique or privileged peculiarity of humans, but as true of all relations between objects whether they involve humans or not. In short, the difference between humans and other objects is not a difference in kind, but a difference in degree."(7)

Here, Levi Bryant lays out two establishing operations. First, the multiplication of significant relations from only those that involve human interpretation to include the entire field of inter-object relations,(8) and second, the leveling of all these relations into the same register in order to preserve their specific characters.(9) Though aimed at the nature–culture divide in particular, this excerpt combats the argument of a world constructed by human experience and intentionality, more generally. By widening the scope of relations to include every sort of relata, object-oriented philosophy calls attention to the huge array of contingent relations that accompany an assemblage. It is not that objects are defined by how they appear to humans, but even strictly cultural objects rely on and involve inorganic objects: “collectives involving humans are always entangled with all sorts of nonhumans without which such collectives could not exist.”(10)

to flickr
Wanmu Orchard, Guangzhou

Nor are objects defined by their relations with one another as a general case, rather object-oriented ontology asserts the more pragmaticist definition that “to be is to make or produce differences” or that “there is not difference that does not make a difference.”(11) Though this seems at first glance to produce a contradiction—being-as-difference must surely be relational, mustn't it?—we draw here from Deleuze's description of difference-in-itself(12) that distinguishes itself from the ground yet without the ground also performing a reciprocal distinction. If “all things equally exist, yet they do not exist equally,”(13) then the question one must answer is how to describe the asymmetry between difference-in-itself and the extrinsic differences between two objects. Deleuze holds that “extensity does not account for the individuations which occur within it.”(14) Thus, in the following, we sketch an outline of the object: first addressing the characteristic of extensive qualities; then defining the role of intensities, or endo-relations, distinct from actualization; and finally unpacking the implications for relations with external objects and the environment. In all this, the goal is to preserve the equal ontological status of individuals and to avoid reductionist arguments that would smooth away the tension between assemblages and their (equally individual) parts.(15)

Notes:

Wednesday, May 14, 2014

A concept for objects

The conceptual advantages of utilizing assemblage urbanism are strongest and most apparent when the urban situation under observation involves surprising or unexpected combinations of objects, actions, and scales.(1) As argued above, preserving the complexity in these situations requires an approach that examines the reality of their entanglements(2) instead of reducing difficult concerns to explanations that conform with familiar structures. The second motivation introduced was to account for the activity of the city, or the agency to act upon it that issues from non-human sources or without human intervention—automatic technological protocols as well as the more quotidian interactions of matter and objects—in order to further advance an ecological definition of the city.(3)

In order to fully describe the city in this way, one also requires a more detailed theory of objects that expands on what assemblage theory provides. Assemblage urbanism is always able to compare against empirical observation to fill in any conceptual gaps, and so tends to produce definitions of assemblages which do not impinge on their objects of observation.(4) This thesis is interested in projective or speculative design practice, anticipating that the designer's empirical research will be less thorough and that objects or object properties may also need to be invented or assumed.(5) In these cases, a stronger conceptual model of how assemblages function and behave as objects is necessary.

to flickr
Longtancun, Guangzhou

In the first chapter, we spoke mostly of how assemblage urbanism reframes the primary aspects of urban studies without spending much time on the description of assemblages themselves. The use of assemblage theory by urbanists primarily as a methodological, and not an ontological, explanation has allowed the notion of the assemblage to remain indistinct. In fact, assemblage urbanism actively promote a less circumscribed invocation as a resistance of pluralism against a dogmatic enforcement of 'proper' use.(6)

From assemblage theory, objects can be characterized as heterogeneous assemblages which cannot be reduced to their parts and whose component elements similarly are not subsumed within the totality of the object. Furthermore, being an element in a larger assemblage does not render an object inferior to the larger assemblage or prevent it from interacting with it directly and independently nor is the larger assemblage considered derivative of its parts. All objects are considered ontologically equal on a flat plane of existence regardless of the size or scale, their complexity or their simplicity.

Expanding on this base, there are three aspects to consider about the assemblage as an object which will be explored through some of the recent philosophical work on object-oriented ontology and developed further by a new reading of monadology which it enables. These three points are the interior existences of objects, the external relations of objects to others and to their environments, and the connection between objects and causation.

Notes:

Tuesday, April 8, 2014

Responsivity: Assemblage Urbanism, and Engagement with the City

The first motivation for enlisting an assemblage urbanism approach is to begin from a model that encourages and valorizes engagement with the city by individuals or groups, by emphasizing the new forms of participation enacted on a continuous basis,(1) and by “countering politically paralyzing pictures of the unity of capital with notions of a more open social field.”(2) So far, we have considered how assemblage urbanism recasts spatial and scalar contexts as effects of assemblage production, how distributed agency destabilizes linear causality and the identity of belonging, and how a flat ontology supports an ecological understanding of the urban through both human and non-human actants. Ultimately, this culminates in a model which cannot discount any assembling action as a source of potential change, but complements these actions with the ability to trace or project possible effects through pragmatic means.(3) Assemblage urbanism pushes us toward an agonistic pluralism(4) expressed by diverse constituencies,(5) but also constructs diverse public places.(6)

to flickr
Longtancun, Guangzhou

In addition, there is a new technological agency, which enforces boundaries, regulates rhythms, and supports infrastructures within the city.(7) Assemblage urbanism enables the city to be thought processually alongside them and to encounter “other powerful social effects of the urban technological unconscious.”(8) Thus, we increase the number of connections between large technical systems while also opening up their functions from within black boxes to illustrate points of articulation(9) and precariousness.(10) Rather than monolithic, controlling entities, technological agency can be located in a prepositional mode of being which “set up what comes next without impinging in the least on what is actually said.”(11) Though this study will not go into topics of real-time sensing and controls,(12) in later sections we will develop this parallel between the procedural enactment of the city and the procedural enactment of code.

As an actively constructive theory,(13) assemblage urbanism, helps mitigate the danger of translating an analytic method into a generative one.(14) The projective nature implict in assemblage theory, of “linking the actual with potential,”(15) makes it more welcoming to design input and the very real impacts which small-scale modifications can bring about. Finally, assemblage urbanism establishes the beginnings of a framework that perpetuates new urban interactions: a reflexive operation by which such impacts feed back into the urban field as immanent causes.(16) Within the urban field, each individual assemblage also functions as an interface for potential engagement.

Notes: